menu Menu
Resist and Revivify. Democratic theory in a time of defiance
By Jean-Paul Gagnon Posted in Democracy, Democratization, Philosophy, Uncategorized on August 21, 2020 0 Comments 23 min read
Huron Socialism: A New Political System Previous Gaddafi and Libya – a case for just intervention? Next

Resist and Revivify: Democratic Theory in a Time of Defiance

Originally published by Democratic Theory, June 2017. Co-authored with Dr Emily Beausoleil.

[I remember preparing the issue of Democratic Theory that this editorial prefaces during a very difficult time, politically. These were the early days of a shock Trump presidency, of a deeply confused Brexit referendum, of a sense that lies, alt-right lullabies, and intolerance were coming to prominence. Emily and I met, before writing this (even before it was in mind), at a conference where I shared this sense of dread. I remember her strength, her uplifting “we can fight and win” attitude—it was so inspiring. I carried that gift of energy from Emily into writing this editorial and then sent it to her for reading. What came back was so much better in tone, in fairness, in measure. Our elders in academia can be so right sometimes in their idioms: great colleagues, courageous friends, are rare diamonds indeed.]

The Economist Intelligence Unit (2017) proclaimed 2016 among the worst
of years for democracy in the world. For the first time since The Economist
Intelligence Unit began reporting its measures of democracy in
2006, the United States has been downgraded to a “flawed democracy.”
Scholars researching contemporary populism have also recently reported
that disaffection with the democratic status quo in countries, including
the United States (Foa and Mounk 2017) and the United Kingdom (Webb
2013), has been growing in volume and shifting in tenor (see, especially,
Moffi tt 2016; Rooduijn 2013; Torre 2015).

We see two main reasons for this disaffection. The first comes down
to the “usual gripes”—lack of trust in politicians (Amnå and Ekman 2014)
and a difficulty in relating to dominant political parties (Gauja 2016: 89)
leading to low voter turnout, especially in subnational elections (Green
and Gerber 2015: 174–177),[1] as well as a sense that certain political practices are behind the times (Innerarity 2010: 52). In the United States and the United Kingdom this disaffection has been amplified by citizens’ responses to the global economic crisis (GEC), which began in 2007 and
whose effects are still being felt.[2]

The second reason is because there is a fragmented, difficult to represent
subset of citizenry in both the United States and the United Kingdom.
These citizens have, to varying extents, been feeling left behind as,
over the last 30 to 40 years, the focus of representative politics moved
from tackling class-based material concerns to ones framed around recognition and identity (Devine and Sensier 2017; Fraser 1995; Fraser and
Honneth 2003). People from these subsets, be they “white working class”
(Ford and Goodwin 2017), the self-professed “silent majority” (Mudde and
Kaltwasser 2017: 11, 84), “angry men” (Kimmel 2013), or “red menace” millennials (Langman and Lundskow 2016: 234), felt unrepresented by
dominant political parties in the GEC’s aftermath. In part humiliated by
lack of work, anxious about their ability—or inability—to pay for housing
and food, and increasingly resentful of a widening inequality gap,
many voters in the United States and the United Kingdom resonated powerfully with antiestablishment and material-focused movements such as the Brexit referendum and both the Donald Trump and Bernie Sanders
presidential campaigns. Job creation, job security (i.e., Louth Leader 2016,
for Brexit, and C-SPAN 2016, for Trump), wealth redistribution (i.e., Warren
2016, for Sanders), and getting big money out of representative politics
were all talking points for proponents of these campaigns.

It is too early for half of the supporters of these populist movements
on either side of the political spectrum in the United States and the
United Kingdom to be labeled “deplorable.”[3] These phenomena are too
complex and will require much unpacking by scholars in the years to
come. Nevertheless, we can confidently make three observations.
The first is that these surges of populist politics from the Left and
Right, and the disaffection that propels them, are rooted in citizens’ sense
of political powerlessness (Stoker and Evans 2014). Whether declining
local industry, employment, and autonomy due to the opaque forces of
a complex global economy (Cowie 2010) or the weakening link between
the challenges of citizens and those in place to represent them (Hay and
Stoker 2009), it is not hard to see why this sense of diminished agency
is currently widespread. Indeed, even those that turn to “deplorable”
responses of scapegoating, aggressive fundamentalisms, and racial and
sexual violence seem to share something of the experience of scarcity,
anxiety, and vulnerability with a far wider public who feel left behind by
both the economy and politics.

This does not excuse these reprehensible, unethical, and antidemocratic
responses. They are deplorable, and those who enact them should
be held to account by their fellow citizens—or, in more extreme cases, by
the rule of law. But it highlights a risk and an opportunity for democratic
politics within such populist movements across the political spectrum.
The second observation is that these anxieties and frustrations are
easily manipulated and harnessed by patently undemocratic leaders. Donald Trump, along with other right-wing populists such as Rodrigo Duterte (Curato 2016) and Benjamin Netanyahu, has styled himself, through his own actions, as one of “the deplorables” (The Economist Intelligence Unit 2017: 1). He has been masterful at addressing, redirecting, and momentarily satisfying intense feelings of frustration, resentment, and shame into deplorable policies that still fail to address (that even, at times, exacerbate) the underlying causes of such sentiments (Watkins 2016). Trump’s first weeks in office have, for example, seen him sign a flurry of executive orders and post numerous tweets that have alienated women, Muslims, environmental activists and researchers, indigenous people, protestors, and immigrants. His actions have provoked widespread condemnation from politicians in other countries, the leaders of major corporations, celebrities, and advocates of prodemocracy movements.
And yet these populist energies, while susceptible, do not inevitably
lend themselves to demagoguery and the othering, scapegoating, and violence that we have seen thus far in Trump’s campaign rhetoric and government orders to date.

Our third observation here is that in such a climate, democratic innovations—reforms that support democracy, in other words—have never been more crucial. First, they can help to better represent those subsets of people who are feeling unrepresented. As Hannah Arendt famously observed regarding the rise of totalitarianism (1968), the unorganized and unrepresented masses do not matter to politics until, suddenly, they do—and more committed, more creative, and more responsive democratic institutions and mechanisms are precisely what is required to address the energies and needs that might, in the absence of a voice, seek more deplorable means elsewhere. Second, democratic processes are uniquely poised to mediate and negotiate between highly diverse and contentious positions—at once a constructive platform for controversial claims as well as a means of publicly challenging and potentially transforming even the most deplorable views. There is perhaps nothing like the alchemy of meaningful exchange between the plurality that is “the people.” Democratic processes, institutions, and sensibilities have never been more necessary, but also in need of signifi cant critique and creativity.

These three observations help us make sense of what a number of democratic theorists, democracy practitioners, and engaged citizens are
doing today. They are applying staunch, evidence-based contrarianism to
resist deplorable people and policies. And they are providing critically informed hope to the prospect of revivifying democratic institutions—such
as political representation—where they have suffered setbacks.
We have seen this mixture before.

In 1939 John Dewey, for instance, wrote his essay “Creative Democracy:
The Task before Us” in a time when brutal violence was overtaking
parts of Europe and East Asia. The essay was Dewey’s response to the populists of his time—Franco, Mussolini, Hitler, Stalin, men who criticized
elites and emphasized the centrality of the people, yet framed “the people”
in homogenous terms. They also convinced their followers that they
were in the midst of a disastrous crisis that only “the leader” could solve
(Rooduijn 2013). Dewey called for the resistance of “intolerance, abuse, calling of names because of differences of opinion about religion or politics
or business, as well as because of differences of race, color, wealth or
degree of culture,” as these actions betrayed “the democratic way of life”
([1939] 1998: 342) as Dewey understood it. But what he found even more
dangerous than open, state-sanctioned coercion against specific groups
of people was the creation of a society in which “common” individuals
do not live a life that actively cultivates civil liberty. This life, as we understand it, is one that tries to lessen the fear and hatred that sometimes
germinates among, and between, people feeling the pinch. It is a life that
uses interpersonal creativity to help others meet their needs and desires.
Put together, Dewey’s resistance against types of violence that are
harmful to democracy and his call to revivify the democratic way of life
defied much of the political reality of his times. His position is defiant
because it cuts both ways: first against what must be resisted—real, existing threats to democracy—and then against problematic political institutions
(ideally the ones that gave oxygen to populist movements in the first place) by advocating for their reform. This defiance advances certain
ideals such as nonviolence, lifelong education, civil liberty, material
equality, precaution, kindness, interpersonal creativity, and the promotion
of societies that are premised on people who help other people meet
their needs and desires without prejudice.

Now, in the shadow of the mainly “alt-right” populist events that
have rocked democracies and democrats across the last 18 months (i.e.,
Duterte, Brexit, Trump, Le Pen), it seems to us that democratic theory has
become acutely defiant once more. As evidenced by this issue, and the
recent literature on populism that we have read, democratic theorists are
actively resisting real threats to democracy and proposing how to resolve
the problems that populists preyed upon to get themselves, and their
movements, across the line.

In this issue, Samuel Salzborn argues that political parties need to
take into account the impermanence of democratic governments and the
understanding that their policy outcomes will likely be revised, replaced,
or repealed in future. This is because a democratic government can only
ever work with the inconsistent, ever-shifting preferences of the always diverse citizens it is representing. It is farcical, therefore, for people to
put their faith in strong leaders who claim that they, and only they, can
make life better for them. As William Caspary (this issue) reminds us, democracy must be about social and communicative action oriented toward
broad consensus formation and re-formation. Democracy, in this sense,
is reminiscent of tidal action—waves of needs and desires from diff erent
aggregations of aff ected and interested citizens crash upon parliaments,
other state institutions, and the media. These waves ultimately wash into contact with other citizens, the waters delighting some and terrifying
others; they may even at times erode the foundations upon which certain
cultural institutions rest. This process of a multimodal, multivocal,
and multipolar pursuit of consensus on a problem-by-problem basis does
not—and cannot—end. If it did it would negate those very conditions
that are vital to the experience of living in a democracy. The lesson from
Salzborn is that populists cannot capture the will of the people, because
it is ephemeral and only ever expressed in part—it is always incomplete.
The waves we see do not defi ne the ocean—a lesson lost on the populist.
Alexandros Kioupkiolis advances an understanding of “common
democracy,” which sees political governance as an aff air that must be
equally accessible to all members of a demos. He comes to argue that
innovations such as “wiki-democracy” (Sirianni 2009: 52; see also Noveck
2015) should be explored, because open-access, collaborative, peer-to-peer
governance holds the potential to overcome the myopias found in contemporary political representation. For Kioupkiolis, the wiki approach is
a practical way of ensuring that more people can meaningfully represent
their concerns by means of an internet-facilitated, autopoetic democracy.
The advantage of Kioupkiolis’s suggestion, for us today, is that it could
reduce the sense of alienation from politics, and inexperience with politics,
that comes from being poorly represented or unrepresented. As
Teun Pauwels (2014: 2) and Daniele Albertazzi and Sean Mueller (2017:
chap. 27) remind us: populists thrive on dissatisfaction with the political
status quo and divisions between the “haves and have-nots.” Any measure
that resists the divisions that political representation creates in a political
community is, therefore, a means to resist the populists that would seek
to use such divisions to their advantage.

Alice el-Wakil comes to the rescue of popular referendums that have
been panned for their unrepresentative and undemocratic procedures
and divisive outcomes (e.g., Parkinson 2001). Brexit, for example, is now
among the most derided of referendums in recent history on account of
its error-prone representation of complex political issues and its rush to
take ill-informed voters to the polls. El-Wakil walks us through Joshua
Cohen’s work to show how a facultative referendum can anticipate these
problems if the referendum’s designers make its procedures more deliberative.

Designing referenda with the deliberative ideal in mind can help
voters and their representatives reach consensus. This in turn means that
the referendum will be more likely to produce an outcome that is more
representative of those people affected by, and interested in, the issue at
hand. Given that populist leaders often thrive off divisions in a political
community, it is sensible practice to try to lessen those instances where
divisions are manufactured through procedure.

Each of these articles proposes various reforms to core democratic
mechanisms (parties, online democracy, referendums). Romand Coles’s
recent book Visionary Pragmatism: Radical and Ecological Democracy in Neoliberal Times (Duke University Press, 2016) takes this impulse to move beyond critique to creative design of democratic practices even further, developing a highly novel account of and set of concrete strategies for a radical democratic politics. This project is timely not only for its answer to the call for committed, creative democratic innovations, but also because it
is focused on enlarging and strengthening democratic life in the neoliberal
context that is greatly responsible for the hollowing-out of the welfare
state, deregulation of the economy, and weakening of representative
politics’ responsiveness to everyday citizens—in a phrase, the underlying
forces driving populist movements and potentially harnessed by dangerous
demagogues. In trickster fashion, Coles identifi es four aspects of this
neoliberal context that obstruct and yet might be co-opted for democratic
purposes: the resonance of receptive generosity to counter the capitalist-evangelical resonance machine; the cultivation of alternative fl ows to counter megacirculation; the co-optation of neoliberal dynamics of co-optation; and the mutually reinforcing oscillation between shocks of exceptional performative eruptions and quotidian organizing and action to counter the dynamics of neoliberalism’s “shock doctrine.” In this, he develops a language and set of specifi c strategies that work to cultivate and sustain a democratic politics from the cellular to the institutional level, in the most hostile of contexts, against the most ostensibly monolithic and impervious of rivals.

This issue’s book symposium on Visionary Pragmatism brings together
a diverse group of scholars to discuss the claims and implications of this
work for political theory and practice. The symposium opens with Paul
Apostolidis, who affirms Coles’s claim that intercorporeal resonance is
central to fostering a sense of agency, creativity, and connection in diverse
polities, but seeks to nuance this with attention to the (class, race,
and imperial) histories and unevenly distributed precarities of laboring
bodies. William Connolly notes that the inability among most academics
to date to make connections across political, physical, aesthetic, and environmental terrains—what Coles achieves uniquely in this book—is partly to blame for their failure to predict the rise of the “alt-right” and Trump. He cautions, however, that complexity theory—translated by Coles into democratic resource—lends itself to the neoliberalism Coles seeks to
challenge, given its ethos of flexibility, self-organization, and creativity.
He invites Coles to interrogate whether this link is inevitable, and how
democrats might draw inspiration and resource from complexity theory
to address the multiple sites and potential coalitions of late capitalism,
and the democratic and ecological crisis of Trump’s election in particular.

Jodi Dean refl ects on the receptivity and resonance harnessed for
antidemocratic ends in Trump’s election: attunement to populist feelings
and transmission of a sense of transformative possibility, embodied
incitations and aff ective intensities at rallies and on social media. She
observes no conceptual tools in Coles’s account to distinguish Trump’s
strategies from those of radical democracy, and warns that an absence
of antagonism—a clear sense of what one is fi ghting against—and an
overly capacious theory encourage an ineff ective “postpolitics.” Indeed,
she argues for a Communist approach as necessary and suffi cient to
achieve the transformation and climate action Coles seeks. Like Connolly
and Dean, Jade Schiff highlights parallels in Coles’s model with
the neoliberal “resonance machine” and the risks therein. She asks how
we might reduce these ever-present risks and work to sustain the highly
demanding radical politics Coles proposes through greater attention to
self-care (what she calls “autoresonance”) in the face of neoliberalism’s
depredations.

The book’s publication lies on one side of the 2016 US election results.
These refl ections, and Romand Coles’s own response, stand on the
other. The “shock” eff ect (to use Coles’s own term) of Trump’s election
shapes the questions, concerns, and urgencies of at least three of these
authors’ commentaries, and as well as addressing the rich and provocative
questions they off er, Coles uses the opportunity to respond to them
in this symposium as a site to apply the book’s innovative approach to
democratic politics to the particular challenges posed by Trump’s administration—what Coles calls (this issue) “the antithesis of an ethos of receptivity called toward complex commonwealth and reciprocal fl ourishing among highly diverse beings.” In short, his response here—like the book itself—seeks to address the all-too-pressing and perplexing question for democratic politics in neoliberal times: “What, then, must we do?”

This issue is rounded out by Democratic Theory’s first “practitioner’s
note.” SeeClickFix is a democratic enterprise coming out of New Haven,
Connecticut. It helps connect local governments and the citizens they are
trying to service. SeeClickFix founder and current CEO Ben Berkowitz
offers a set of optimistic notes from the field. With more than a million
users reporting issues to hundreds of local governments and public and
private organizations (the company recently reported that there were
nearly 100,000 user reports in 2016 alone—most dealing with graffiti concerns), SeeClickFix seems to be fulfilling a number of the premonitions
that have come out of the democracy 2.0 literature (e.g., McNutt 2014;
Stamati et al. 2015). The “democratic innovations economy” is certainly
a space for scholars to watch, and we hope to be bringing more notes of
this kind to you in future issues.

The field of democratic theory is blossoming with strategies to resist
violence against democracy and to revivify those democratic institutions
that would benefit from conceptual and/or practical reform. We find ourselves not in a period of democratic despondency and political disarray,
as less circumspect cynics would have it, but rather in a vitalizing time
of defiance. There is power in this. To defy in the name of democracy is to
oppose “truthiness,” confront arbitrary decision making, disobey illogic,
and dissent from any policy that will, to use Dewey’s phraseology, constitute
treason to our democratic ways of life. A time of defiance invites us
all to be daring in our compassion for each other, bold in how we explore
and care for the many—and diverse—meanings of democracy,4 audacious
in our gentleness toward the earth, and courageous in our advocacy
for that paradoxical but poignant practice of democratizing democracy
wheresoever and whensoever this need should arise.

Notes

  1. The lack of attention given to subnational, particularly local, elections in democracies such as Australia, Canada, the United Kingdom, and the United States is, on the one hand, understandable, as these elections receive far less fanfare in the media, but on the other, this phenomenon is perplexing because it is typically our local politicians who affect our daily lives the most. For more, see Chou (2016).
  2. Cheng Enfu and Xie Chang’an (2016) and Hinkson (2016) mention that the GEC is still affecting Western capitalist democracies. See, comparatively, for Australia, Borowski (2013) and Carvalho (2015: 37).
  3. McCann (2016: 46) reports how Hillary Clinton, “at a September LGBT fundraiser in Manhattan,” said “half of Trump’s supporters” belong in a “basket of deplorables.” While some of Trump’s supporters are likely to have behaved in deplorable ways, there is insufficient data to claim that half of those who ended up voting for him are deplorable.
  4. Gagnon (2016) has identified more than 1,216 real, existing descriptors of democracy. This list of adjectives sustains the understanding that democracy has hundreds, if not thousands, of different definitions, meanings, theories, conceptions, models, practices, iterations, and so forth, which come to us from different times and spaces.

References

Albertazzi, Daniele, and Sean Mueller. 2017. “Populism and Liberal Democracy: Populists in Government in Austria, Italy, Poland and Switzerland.” Government and Opposition 48 (3): 343–371.

Amnå, Erik, and Joakim Ekman. 2013. “Standby Citizens: Diverse Faces of Political Passivity.” European Political Science Review 6 (2): 261–281.

Arendt, Hannah. 1968. The Origins of Totalitarianism. Orlando: Harcourt.

Borowski, Allan. 2013. “Risky by Design: The Mandatory Private Pillar of Australia’s Retirement Income System.” Social Policy & Administration 47: 749–764.

Carvalho, Patrick. 2015. “Youth Unemployment in Australia.” Policy: A Journal of Public Policy and Ideas 31 (4): 36–43.

Chou, Mark. 2016. “To Make Your Voice Count, Be a Local Hero.” Herald Sun, 20 October. http://ow.ly/HmAN308MeS8.

Coles, Romand. 2016. Visionary Pragmatism: Radical and Ecological Democracy in Neoliberal Times. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

Cowie, Jeff erson. 2010. Stayin’ Alive: The 1970s and the Last Days of the Working Class. New York: New Press.

C-SPAN. 2016. “Donald Trump Campaign Rally in Wilmington Ohio.” 1 September. http://ow.ly/CzUz308FmYI.

Curato, Nicole. 2016. “Politics of Anxiety, Politics of Hope: Penal Populism and Duterte’s Rise to Power.” Journal of Current Southeast Asian Affairs 35 (3): 91–109.

Torre, Carlos de la, ed. 2015. The Promise and Perils of Populism: Global Perspectives. Lexington: University of Kentucky Press.

Devine, Fiona, and Marianne Sensier. 2017. “Class, Politics and the Progressive Dilemma.” The Political Quarterly 88 (1): 30–38.

Dewey, John. (1939) 1998. “Creative Democracy: The Task before Us.” Pp. 340–344 in The Essential Dewey: Pragmatism, Education, Democracy, vol. 1, ed. Larry A. Hickman and Thomas M. Alexander. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Enfu, Cheng, and Xie Chang’an. 2016. “American Democracy, World Peace, and the China Model—A Critical Analysis of Francis Fukuyama’s ‘At the “End of History” Still Stands Democracy.’” International Critical Thought 6 (1): 1–12.

Foa, Roberto Stefan, and Yascha Mounk. 2017. “The Signs of deconsolidation.” Journal of Democracy 28 (1): 5–15.

Ford, Robert, and Matthew Goodwin. 2017. “A Nation Divided.” Journal of Democracy 28 (1): 17–30.

Fraser, Nancy. 1995. “From Redistribution to Recognition? Dilemmas of Justice in a ‘Post-Socialist’ Age.” New Left Review 1 (212): 68–93.

Fraser, Nancy, and Axel Honneth. 2003. Redistribution or Recognition? A Political Philosophical Exchange. London: Verso.

Gagnon, Jean-Paul. 2016. “Democracy’s Adjective Pluralism.” Conference paper. Presented at the Australian Political Studies Association’s annual conference, hosted by the University of New South Wales (Sydney), 26–28 September. http://ow.ly/ndNY308GFfz.

Gauja, Anika. 2016. Political Parties and Elections: Legislating for Representative Democracy. London: Routledge.

Green, Donald P., and Alan S. Gerber. 2015. Get Out the Vote: How to Increase Voter Turnout. Washington DC: Brookings Institution Press.

Hay, Colin, and Gerry Stoker. 2009. “Revitalising Politics: Have We Lost the Plot?” Representation 45 (3): 225–236.

Hinkson, John. 2016. “Globalization and the New World Order.” Arena Journal 45/46: 51–73.

Innerarity, Daniel. 2010. The Transformation of Politics: Governing in the Age of Complex Societies. Brussels: Peter Lang.

Kimmel, Michael. 2013. Angry White Men: American Masculinity at the End of an Era. New York: Nation Books.

Langman, Lauren, and George Lundskow. 2016. God, Guns, Gold and Glory: American Character and Its Discontents. Leiden: Brill.

Louth Leader. 2016. “Lincolnshire Politicians: ‘Why We Should Leave the EU.’” 22 June. http://ow.ly/UVWf308FlAP.

McCann, Daryl. 2016. “Battlers Against the System: Populist Critiques of Hillary Clinton.” Quadrant 60 (11): 44–46.

McNutt, Kathleen. 2014. “Public Engagement in the Web 2.0 Era: Social Collaborative Technologies in a Public Sector Context.” Canadian Public Administration 57 (1): 49–70.

Moffitt, Benjamin. 2016. The Global Rise of Populism: Performance, Political Style, and Representation. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Mudde, Cas, and Cristobal Rovira Kaltwasser. 2017. Populism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Noveck, Beth Simone. 2015. Smart Citizens, Smarter State: The Technologies of Expertise and the Future of Governing. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Pauwels, Teun. 2014. Populism in Western Europe: Comparing Belgium, Germany and the Netherlands. London: Routledge.

Parkinson, John. 2001. “Deliberative Democracy and Referendums.” Pp. 131–152 in Challenges to Democracy: Ideas, Involvement and Institutions, ed. Keith M. Dowding, Jim Hughes, and Helen Margetts. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

Rooduijn, Matthijs. 2013. “The Nucleus of Populism: In Search of the Lowest Common Denominator.” Government and Opposition 49 (4): 572–598.

Sirianni, Carmen. 2009. Investing in Democracy: Engaging Citizens in Collaborative Governance. Washington DC: Brookings Institution Press.

Stamati, Teta, Thanos Papadopoulos, and Dimosthenis Anagnostopoulos. 2015. “Social Media for Openness and Accountability in the Public Sector: Cases in the Greek Context.” Government and Information Quarterly 32 (1): 12–29.

Stoker, Gerry, and Mark Evans. “The ‘Democracy-Politics Paradox’: The Dynamics of Political Alienation.” Democratic Theory 1 (2): 26–36.

The Economist Intelligence Unit. 2017. “Democracy Index 2016: Revenge of ‘the Deplorables.’” The Economist Intelligence Unit Limited.

Warren, Michael. 2016. “At the Root of Recent Political Upheavals in Several Countries Is the Growing Gap between the Rich and the Rest.” Huron Expositor, 26 October, A4.

Watkins, Mary. 2016. “The Social and Political Life of Shame in the U.S. Presidential Election 2016.” Unpublished paper presented at “Shame and the Experience of Class in the U.S.,” Massachusetts Institute for Psychoanalysis and the Psychosocial Work Group of the Psychology and the Other Institute, Cambridge, MA, 19 October.

Webb, Paul. 2013. “Who Is Willing to Participate? Dissatisfied Democrats, Stealth Democrats, and Populists in the United Kingdom.” European Journal of Political Research 52 (6): 747–772.

democracy democratic theory Emily Beausoleil Jean-Paul Gagnon philosophy of democracy


Previous Next

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Cancel Post Comment

keyboard_arrow_up